• Sonuç bulunamadı

A theory of a heterogeneous divisible commodity exchange economy

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "A theory of a heterogeneous divisible commodity exchange economy"

Copied!
6
0
0

Yükleniyor.... (view fulltext now)

Tam metin

(1)

Contents lists available atScienceDirect

Journal of Mathematical Economics

j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e :w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / j m a t e c o

A theory of a heterogeneous divisible commodity exchange economy

Farhad Husseinov

Department of Economics, Bilkent University, 06800 Bilkent, Ankara, Turkey

a r t i c l e i n f o

Article history: Received 12 March 2010

Received in revised form 26 October 2010 Accepted 3 December 2010

Available online 14 December 2010

JEL classification: D51

C71 Keywords:

Heterogeneous divisible commodity Exchange economy

Land trading economy Competitive equilibrium Core

Fair division

a b s t r a c t

In theoretical land economics the existence of a competitive equilibrium with an additive price is consid-ered problematic. This paper studies the exchange and allocation of a heterogeneous divisible commodity such as land, which is modeled as a measurable space. In a ‘land’ trading economy with unordered convex preferences, the existence of a competitive equilibrium with an additive equilibrium price is proved. This paper demonstrates also the existence of a weak core and a fair allocation.

© 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction

We consider the exchange of a heterogeneous divisible com-modity, such as land, which is modeled as a measurable space (X, ). In theoretical models of land economics, X is assumed to be a Borel measurable subset of the Euclidean space R2(or more

gen-erally, Rk) and to be the Borel -algebra B(X) of subsets of X.

It is usual to consider this measurable space with the Lebesgue measure. The existence of a competitive equilibrium with addi-tive prices in land trading has been an issue in theoretical land economics; this is the central question that the present paper addresses.

The first study of competitive equilibria in the traditions of general equilibrium theory (à la Arrow-Debreu), in a land-trading economy is due toBerliant (1985). He shows the existence of a competitive equilibrium when preferences over land parcels are represented by utility functions of the form U(B) =



Bu(x)dx, so

that U is a measure onB(X) absolutely continuous with respect

夽 I am grateful to the participants of the session in the International Conference on Game Theory at Stony Brook, July 10–14, 2006, where results of an early draft of this paper were presented, for useful discussions. I am also grateful to Nedim Alemdar and Ozgur Evren for many useful comments and a referee for many useful suggestions that led to a number of improvments.

∗ Tel.: +90 312 2902228; fax: +90 312 266 5140. E-mail address:farhad@bilkent.edu.tr

to the Lebesgue measure. His proof uses a method that imbeds the land-trading economy into an economy with the commodity space L(X), and then usesBewley’s (1972)equilibrium existence results along with methods of infinite dimensional analysis.

Dunz (1991)studies the existence of the core in a land-trading economy for substantially more general preferences. In this paper preferences are represented by the utility functions that are com-positions of quasi-concave functions with a finite number of parcel characteristics. Dunz proves that under these assumptions on pref-erences the weak core of a land-trading game is nonempty. These characteristics are countably additive over land parcels. Assign-ing a finite number of additive characteristics to land parcels is a common assumption made in empirical literature on land trading.

Dunz (1991), based on results of his joint work withBerliant and Dunz’s (1986), argues that “...if prices are required to be additive... then an equilibrium might not exist. If no equilibrium with addi-tive prices exists, then it is not clear what the final allocation of the economy will be since there would always be arbitrage opportuni-ties. This suggests that competitive equilibrium might not be the appropriate solution concept for economies with land.” However, nonexistence of equilibrium inBerliant and Dunz’s (1986) exam-ple is of the same nature as one in the classical case of trading divisible commodities and is due to nonconvexity of preferences. One of the goals of the present paper is to show that a competitive equilibrium with an additive price exists in a land-trading econ-omy with rather general unordered ‘convex’ preferences. In fact,

0304-4068/$ – see front matter © 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.jmateco.2010.12.001

(2)

this is done in the more abstract context of a measurable-space-trading economy. We show the existence of an equilibrium where the equilibrium price is a measure,, on (X, ), absolutely con-tinuous with respect to the sum of all characteristic measures. For the land-trading economy, where all characteristic measures are assumed to be absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure, we obtain that the equilibrium price  is also abso-lutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure. Hence, the Radon–Nikodim derivative (d/d) is an integrable function h on the measure space (X,, ) (seeAliprantis and Border, 1994, p. 350). So(B) =



Bh(x)d(x) for all measurable sets B in X. Here the

function h can be interpreted as the equilibrium price density on X. In a related paperBerliant and Dunz (2004)(henceforth, BD) study the existence of equilibrium in a model where the shape and location of land parcels affect agents’ preferences. While BD assume complete and transitive preferences, we do not employ these assumptions in the present paper. Another difference between the two papers is that preferences in BD are defined directly on the -algebra of land pieces, whereas here they are defined through characteristic measures of land pieces. The use of the characteristic measures allows us to formulate the convexity of agents’ prefer-ences in a straightforward way. By contrast, the existence theorem of BD utilizes a novel ‘convexity’ condition called ‘separation by hyperplanes’ which is assumed for nonwasteful partitions. More-over, they assume the existence of nonwasteful partitions. Actually, the last two assumptions are joint assumptions on agents’ prefer-ences. Thus, there are significant conceptual and methodological differences between the two papers.

Using the standard scheme, in this paper we also show that, a competitive allocation is a weak core allocation. This core existence result generalizes existing core existence results in two direc-tions: first, it considers the division problem in the setting of an abstract measurable space and does not assume a certain refer-ence measure, and second, preferrefer-ences are not assumed to be ordered.

The next topic dealt with in this paper is the existence of a fair division. Examples of the fair division problem include dividing an inheritance fairly among the inheritors, and designing land reform laws that allow dividing land owned by a collective farm fairly among its members in transition economies. On a deeper level, fairness can be regarded as an essential and a desirable property of a solution concept in economics (and game theory).

Weller (1985) considers a problem of fair division of a

mea-surable space (X,) with a finite number of atomless measures

describing agents’ preferences over measurable subsets. He shows the existence of an envy-free and efficient partition of this problem. In a somewhat different setting, namely when X is a measurable

subset of the Euclidean space Rk and preference measures are

nonatomic and absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure, Berliant et al. (1992)show the existence of a group-envy-free and efficient partition. The concept of a group-group-envy-free partition is stronger than the concept of an envy-free partition. However, neither of these results implies the other. Weller’s result is concerned with the more abstract problem of fair partitioning an abstract measurable space with no reference measure. On the other hand,Berliant et al. (1992)prove the existence of a fair par-tition in a stronger sense. Our approach to the fairness problem is abstract and we will consider much more general preferences over measurable pieces. The result established here contains both of the above-discussed results.

We would like to stress that all the results of this paper assume rather general classes of preferences over measurable pieces. The importance of considering such preferences in the present context has been indicated by students of heterogeneous commodity mar-kets. For example,Chambers (2005)notes that “working with more

general domains of utility functions should be a motivating goal in this model.”

In proving the existence of a competitive equilibrium we use the following scheme: first, we show that the problem of exchange of a heterogeneous divisible commodity is reducible to that of a finite number of homogeneous divisible commodities (totality of subjectively attributed characteristics of measurable pieces), where endowments are subsets in the commodity space rather than commodity bundles. Then we transform this economy into the general model introduced byGale and Mas-Colell (1975), and thereby employ their competitive equilibrium existence theorem. This introduction is followed by a section that introduces basic concepts and some preliminary results. In Section3we present our central results on the existence of a competitive equilibrium and nonemptiness of the core in a measurable-space-trading economy. Section4studies fairness criteria for this economy. In Appendix A we state a classical theorem on convexity of the range of a vector-measure mapping, defined on partitions of a measurable space that is used in the proofs of the main results. Appendix B is devoted to the proofs of the main results.

2. Preliminaries

We model a measurable space trading problem in the follow-ing way. Let (X,) be a measurable space (a cake or land plot) and let P ={A1, A2,. . ., An} be a measurable ordered partition of X. Let

1,2,. . ., n be nonatomic finite vector measures on (X,) of

dimensions s1, s2,. . ., sn, respectively.ji(j = 1, . . . , si) will denote

the j-th component of vector-measurei. The interpretation is that

there are n persons, denoted as 1, 2,. . ., n, each contributing his share Ai(i∈ N = {1, 2, . . ., n}) to the cake X, and pieces of the cake

are valued by individuals according to their measures1,2,. . .,

n, respectively. The components of vectori(B) are interpreted

as measures of different (possibly subjective) attributes of a mea-surable piece B, attached to this piece by individual i. We assume that individual i has a preferenceiover his subjective attributes

profilesi(B), B∈ , and hence over measurable sets B ∈ . We will

use the same symbolifor denoting both of these preferences. No

confusion should arise. Every ordered measurable division{B1,. . .,

Bn} of X will be interpreted as a feasible allocation of X. All divisions

considered further are assumed to be ordered and measurable. An alternative interpretation is that initially individuals possess land parcels A1,. . ., An, respectively, and they exchange pieces of land

to improve their welfare.

Definition 2.1. A pair (P = {B1, B2,. . ., Bn}, ) consisting of a

divi-sion P and a measure  is a competitive equilibrium if for each individual i the subset Bimaximizes his preferenceion his budget

set

Bi() = {B ∈  | (B) ≤ (Ai)}.

In this case, the division P is called an equilibrium allocation and the measure is called an equilibrium price.

A coalition is an arbitrary nonempty subset of N. The set of all coalitions is denoted asN.

Definition 2.2. A coalition I⊂ N improves (weakly improves) upon a division P ={B1, B2, . . ., Bn} if there exists a

divi-sion Q ={Ci| i∈ I} of A(I) = ∪i∈IAi such that CiiBifor all i∈ I (not

BiiCifor all i∈ I and CiiBiat least for one i∈ I.)

Definition 2.3. Division P = {B1, B2,. . ., Bn} is a weak core allocation

(core allocation) if no coalition improves (weakly improves) upon P. The set of all (weak) core allocations is the (weak) core of the measurable space trading economy.

(3)

Next, we introduce two concepts of Pareto efficiency of a divi-sion.

Definition 2.4. Division P ={B1, B2,. . ., Bn} of X is weak Pareto

efficient (Pareto efficient) if there is no divisionP = {B

1, B 2, . . . , B n}

of X such thati(B i)ii(Bi) for all i∈ N (not BiiB ifor alli ∈ N and

B

iiBifor at least one i∈ N).

We will identify a vector of vectors (perhaps of different dimen-sions) as a long vector with scalar coordinates arranged in the lexicographic order. Sometimes we will denote coordinates with double indexes, the first showing the component vector and the second showing the component in that component vector.

3. Existence of a competitive equilibrium and core

In this section for preferences i(i∈ N) on the

nonnega-tive orthant, Rs+i, in the Euclidean space Rsi we denote P

i(xi)=

{x

i∈ Rs+i|x iixi}. Clearly, the correspondence Pidefinesiin a unique

way. We do not assume preferences iare complete or

transi-tive. We assume that preferencesi, i∈ N, are continuous (that is,

graphs of correspondences Piare open relative toRs+i× Rs+i) and

con-vex (that is, the upper contour sets, Pi(xi), are convex for arbitrary

characteristics vectorsxi∈ Rs+i, i ∈ N).

As usual for vectors x = (x1,. . ., xm), y = (y1,. . ., ym) in Rmwe write

x≥ y if xi≥ yifor all i = 1,. . ., m. We write x > y if x ≥ y and x /= y, and

x y if xi> yifor all i = 1,. . ., m.

We will assume also that preferences are monotonic: if xi, x i∈ Rs+i, xi ≥ xi, then Pi(x i)⊂ Pi(xi).

We assume the following about the initial endowments of the individuals.

Assumption. (Positive Endowments)

For each i∈ N, the set Aican be divided into n measurable parts

Aij(j∈ N) such that j(Aij) 0 for all j ∈ N.

One property, with a clear economic interpretation, that is suffi-cient for fulfilment of the positive endowments assumption may be formulated in terms of mutual continuity of measuresi(i∈ N).

For two measures and  defined on the same domain, is called absolutely continuous with respect to if (A) = 0 implies  (A) = 0.

It is easily seen that if for each i∈ N there exists j ∈ {1, . . ., si} such

thatji(Ai)> 0 and all the component measures are absolutely

con-tinuous with respect to each other, then the assumption of positive endowments is satisfied.

The central result of this paper is the following competitive equilibrium existence theorem.

Theorem 3.1. If the attribute vector-measures i, i∈ N, are

nonatomic, and preferences i, i∈ N, are irreflexive, continuous,

monotone and convex, and the positive endowments assumption is satisfied, then there exists a competitive equilibrium (P ={B1, B2,. . .,

Bn}, ) in the measurable space trading economy. Moreover, the

equi-librium price measure is absolutely continuous with respect to the sum of all component measures of vector-measuresi, i∈ N.

Proof of this theorem will be given in Appendix B.

Corollary 3.2. Under the assumptions of Theorem3.1the weak core in the measurable space trading economy is nonempty.

Proof. It is easy to see that a competitive equilibrium allocation

{B1, B2,. . ., Bn} belongs to the weak core. Assume on the contrary,

that there exists a coalition I that improves upon partition{B1, B2,

. . ., Bn}. Thus there exists a partition {Ci| i∈ I} of A(I) = ∪i∈IAisuch

that CiiBifor all i∈ I. Then since ({B1, B2,. . ., Bn}, ) is an

equilib-rium we have(Ci) >(Bi) for all i∈ I. Adding these inequalities we

will get(C(I)) > (A(I)). This contradicts to C(I) = A(I). 

Hüsseinov (2008) shows that under the assumptions of nonatomicity of characteristic measuresi(i∈ N), and

rational-ity, continuity and convexity of preferences, the weak core of the heterogeneous divisible commodity exchange economy is nonempty. In Corollary3.2preferences are not assumed to be ratio-nal. Instead, monotonicity of preferences and positive endowments are assumed.

It follows from Theorem 5 inHüsseinov (2008)that if in addi-tion to the assumpaddi-tions of Theorem3.1preferences are rational and measures



si

j=1ji(i ∈ N) are absolutely continuous with respect to

each other, then the weak core and the core coincide. From this observation and Corollary3.2it follows that under these assump-tions the core is nonempty.

The following proposition is proved inHüsseinov (2008, see Theorem 5).

Proposition 3.3. If preferences i are the strict parts of

ratio-nal continuous weak preferencesi, monotone (forxi, xi ∈ Rs+i, x i>

xiimpliesxi ixi,) and if measures i=



sj=1i ji(i ∈ N) are absolutely

continuous with respect to each other, then the weak core and the core coincide.

Corollary3.2and Proposition3.3imply

Corollary 3.4. If in addition to the assumptions of Proposition

3.3preferences are convex and positive endowments assumption is satisfied, then the core in the measurable space trading economy is nonempty.

4. Existence of fair divisions

Definition 4.1. A division P = {A1, A2,. . ., An} of X is fair if it is

(a) weakly Pareto efficient, that is, if there is no other division Q ={C1, C2,. . ., (Cn)} such that i(Ci)∈ Pi(i(Ai)) for i∈ N, and

(b) envy-free, that is, if i(Aj)/∈ Pi(i(Ai)) [in other words, not

AjiAi] for all i, j∈ N.

We define now a stronger version of the last concept.

Definition 4.2. A division{A1, A2,. . ., An} is weak

group-envy-free if for any pair of coalitions N1, N2with |N1| = | N2| there is no

division{Ci}i ∈ N1of∪j ∈ N2Ajsuch that Ci∈ Pi(Ai) for all i∈ N1. This definition is adapted fromBerliant et al. (1992). Obviously, if an allocation is weak-group envy-free then it is envy-free and weakly Pareto efficient.

Definition 4.2 . A division {A1, A2,. . ., An} is group-envy-free if for

any pair of coalitions N1, N2 with |N1| = | N2| there is no division

{Ci}i ∈ N1of∪j ∈ N2Ajsuch that Ai/∈ Pi(Ci) for all i∈ N1and Ci∈ Pi(Ai) at least for one i∈ N1.

Of course when preferences Piare derived from rational weak

preferencesi, (equivalently,iare negative transitive and

asym-metric), then the last part of Definition 4.2 reads as CiiAifor alli ∈ N1 and CiiAiat least for one i ∈ N1.

As in Proof of Proposition 3.3 it can be shown that under the assumptions of this proposition every weak group-envy-free divi-sion is group-envy-free, that is, the two concepts coincide.

Theorem 4.4. Under the assumptions of Theorem3.1there exists a weak group-envy-free and weakly Pareto efficient allocation.

(4)

Let ji, i ∈ N be nonatomic measures on (X, ). If there had existed a partition of X into n parts, say Cj, j∈ N, so that

restric-tions of vector-measure = (1,2,. . ., n) into sets Cj, j∈ N have

identical ranges, then one could exploit the standard scheme of a proof of the existence of a fair division by assigning each individual j the piece Cj. The author does not know whether such a partition

exists, therefore we are not able to derive the existence of a fair division from the existence of an equilibrium division.

For proving the existence of a fair (or more generally, a group-envy-free and efficient) allocation, we will use the aforementioned method that we also use to establish the existence of a competitive equilibrium: We will first construct an economy with an aggregate endowment set, and then generate from it the type of economy as inGale and Mas-Colell (1975), in which individuals are given equal profits. We will then use a competitive equilibrium of the latter economy for constructing a division in the measurable space division problem that is group-envy-free and Pareto efficient.

When X is a subset of the Euclidean space Rkand preferences i

are given by scalar Borel measures on X, absolutely continuous with respect to the Lebesgue measure, Theorem 4.1 reduces to Theorem 2 ofBerliant et al. (1992). It should be noted that in their approach they start with a special reference measure (the Lebesgue measure), while our approach does not assume any such a priori measure.

Theorem 4.1 implies the following corollary:

Corollary 4.5. Under the assumptions of Theorem3.1there exists a fair division of a measurable space (X,).

Finally, let us also note that if each agent i has a single attribute formalized as a finite positive measureion and preferences

defined simply as strictly greater relation on R (which is the same as saying that preferences are given by scalar measures on), then Corollary 4.2 is reduced toWeller’s (1985)fairness result.

Appendix A. Chernoff’s theorem

The following theorem is a generalization of a result known as Dubins–Spanier’s theorem (see alsoAliprantis and Border, 1994, p. 358) and easily follows from this result. It is to be noted that, in fact, this theorem was discovered a decade earlier byChernoff (1951). Both of these theorems are consequences of the celebrated Liapunov Theorem (Liapunov, 1940).

Theorem A. Let (X, ) be a measurable space and let 1,2,. . .,

nbe nonatomic finite vector measures on (X,) of dimensions s1, s2,

. . ., sn, respectively. Then the following set in Rs, wheres =



nj=1sj,

R = {(i(Bi))ni=1∈ Rs| P = (B1, B2, . . . , Bn) is a division ofX}

is compact and convex.

Proof of Theorem A is based on the Dubins–Spanier’s theorem.

Let = (k)sk=1be a vector measure (1,2,. . ., n) of dimension

s. With every division P = (B1, B2,. . ., Bn)∈ n(X) we associate the

s× n matrix of reals M(P) = (k(Bi)). Denote by Ms×nthe space of

all s× n matrices with real entries. By Theorem 1 inDubins and Spanier (1961)the rangeR ⊂ Ms×nof the matrix-valued function

M is compact and convex.

Let L : Ms×n→ Rsbe a mapping defined in the following way: The

first s1components of L(M) are the first s1entries in the first column

of matrix M, the second s2components are the entries in the second

column of M with the column indexes s1+ 1 through s1+ s2, and so

on. Clearly, L is a linear mapping withL(R )= R. Since R is compact and convex it follows that so isR. 

Appendix B. Proofs of main results

Proof of Theorem 3.1. We will reduce the above exchange

econ-omy to an econecon-omy of exchange of a finite number of divisible homogeneous commodities, where endowments of individuals are sets in the consumption spaces, rather than commodity bundles, from which the individuals are free to choose.

There are s commodities in this economy. Thus the commodity space is Rs, the s-dimensional Euclidean space.Rs

+andR++s denote

the nonnegative and positive cones in this space, respectively. For i ∈ N, Rs+iwill be the consumption space of individual i, which we consider as a subset inRs

+.

We define the initial endowment set Ei⊂ Rsof individual i in the

following way:

Ei= {(1(C1), 2(C2), . . . , n(Cn))| {C1, C2, . . . , Cn} is a partition of Ai}.

By Theorem A the initial endowment sets are compact and con-vex.

Denote by the unit simplex in Rs. A price p = (ps1,. . ., psn), where psiis the price associated with consumer i, will be an element of . Given a price p ∈ , the wealth of individual i is defined as ˛i(p) = max{p · x | x ∈ Ei} for all i ∈ N,

where p· x is the scalar product of vectors p and x. The budget set of i is defined as

Bi(p) = {x ∈ Rsi| psi· x ≤ ˛i(p)}.

Preferences of individual i are defined through mapping Pi:

Rs+i→ Rs+i which is irreflexive, that is,xi/∈ Pi(xi) for allxi∈ R+si, has

an open graph inRs+i× Rs+iand nonempty convex values.

We denote byE the exchange economy involving n individuals

1,. . ., n, their endowment sets E1,. . ., En, and preferences P1. . . ,

Pn, respectively.

Define the set of aggregate endowment vectors as the algebraic sum of individual endowment sets, E =



i∈NEi, and the technology

set asY = E + Rs −.

Proof of the following fact is a straightforward exercise.

Fact 1. Y is closed and has a nonempty bounded intersection with

the nonnegative coneRs +.

Let E0⊂ E be the Pareto frontier of Y, in other words, the smallest

set withY = E0+ R−s.

Definition B1. A competitive equilibrium in economy E is defined

as an (2N + 1)-tuple (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ˆy1, ˆy2, . . . , ˆyn, ¯p) ∈ ((i ∈ NRs+i)×

(i ∈ NEi))× such that ¯ x0=



i ∈ N ¯ xi=



i ∈ N ˆ yi= ˆy0∈ E0, (1) ¯ p · ¯xi= ¯p · ˆyi= ˛i( ¯p) for i ∈ N, (2) and P(¯xi)∩ Bi( ¯p) = ∅ for i ∈ N. (3) Define (p) = sup p · Y for p ∈ . (4)

Obviously the supremum in formula(4) is attained for each

p∈ .

Proof of the following fact is a straightforward exercise.

(5)

By the definitions of Y and E we have

(p) =



i ∈ N

˛i(p) for p ∈ . (5)

(This is known as ‘aggregation’ in Microeconomics; seeMas-Colell et al., 1995, Proposition 5.E.1). Following Gale and Mas-Colell (1975)observe that ¯ p · ˆy0=



i ∈ N ¯ p · ˆyi=



i ∈ N ˛i( ¯p) = max ¯p · Y.

By the positive endowments assumption, Eicontains a strictly

positive vector. Hence

˛i(p) > 0 for all p ∈ , i ∈ N.

Now we have the following economy

E0= {(Rsi, Pi, ˛i)i ∈ N, Y}

satisfying all of the assumptions of Gale–Mas-Colell existence theo-rem (1975). So there exists an (N + 1)− tuple (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p) such

that the following relations are satisfied:



i ∈ N ¯ xi= ¯x0∈ Y, (6) ¯ p · ¯xi= ˛i( ¯p) for i ∈ N, (7) and P(¯xi)∩ Bi( ¯p) = ∅ for i ∈ N. (8)

Next we will show that for every competitive equilibrium (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p) in E0 (that is for every vector (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p)

satisfying conditions (6)–(8)), there exist ˆyi, i∈ N such that

(¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ˆy1, ˆy2, . . . , ˆyn, ¯p) is a competitive equilibrium in E.

In this step we make use of the monotonicity assumption. So let (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p) be a competitive equilibrium in E0. Then



i ∈ Nx¯i= ¯x0∈ Y. If ¯x0∈ E0, then since E0⊂ E ¯ x0=



i ∈ N ¯ xi=



i ∈ N ˆ yi

for some ˆyi∈ Ei(i∈ N). Since ¯p · ¯x0= max ¯p · Y it follows that Eq.(2)

are satisfied. Thus (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ˆy1, ˆy2, . . . , ˆyn, ¯p) is a competitive

equilibrium inE. Assume ¯x0/∈ E0. It follows from the definitions

of Y and E0that there exists ˆx0∈ E0such that ˆx0≥ ¯x0. Set ˆxi= ¯xi+

(ˆx0− ¯x0)sifori ∈ N. Then



i ∈ N ˆ xi=



i ∈ N ¯ xi+



i ∈ N (ˆx0− ¯x0)si= ˆx0. So (ˆx1, ˆx2, . . . , ˆxn) is feasible. We also have ¯ p · ˆxi= ¯p · ¯xi= ˛i( ¯p) for i ∈ N.

Indeed, ˆxi≥ ¯xiimplies ¯p · ˆxi≥ ¯p · ¯xi= ˛i( ¯p) for all i. It is not

pos-sible that ¯p · ˆxj> ¯p · ˆxjfor some j; for otherwise, we would have

¯ p ·



i ∈ N ˆ xi=



i ∈ N ¯ p · ˆxi>



i ∈ N ¯ p · ¯xi=



i ∈ N ˛i( ¯p) = max ¯p · Y.

This is a contradiction since vectors ˆxiform a feasible allocation.

Therefore ¯p · ˆxi≤ ¯p · ¯xiand hence ¯p · ˆxi= ¯p · ¯xifor all i.

Since ˆxi≥ ¯xi, by the monotonicity assumption it follows that

Pi(ˆxi)⊂ Pi(¯xi). This inclusion, together with Eq.(8)imply that

Pi(ˆxi)∩ Bi( ¯p) = ∅ for i ∈ N.

So, we have constructed a new competitive equilibrium (ˆx1, ˆx2, . . . , ˆxn, ¯p) in E0such that



i ∈ N

ˆ

xi= ˆx0∈ E0.

We have shown above how to construct a competitive equilib-rium inE from one in E0with this property. Thus, we have proven

the existence of a competitive equilibrium in economyE.

Let (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ˆy1, ˆy2, . . . , ˆyn, ¯p) be a competitive

equilibrium in the economy E. By the definition of sets

Ei(i∈ N) there are divisions Pi= {A1i, A2i, . . . , Ani} of sets Ai

such that (1(A1i), 2(A2i), . . . , n(An

i))= ˆyi for each i∈ N. Set

Bj= ∪i ∈ NAji(j ∈ N). Clearly, {B1, B2,. . ., Bn} is a division of X. Define

a measure on  by setting

(D) =



i ∈ N

¯

psi· i(D ∩ Bi) for D ∈ .

Obviously is a measure on  that is absolutely continuous with respect to =



i ∈ N



si

j=1ji. We will show that the pair

({B1, B2,. . ., Bn}, ) is a competitive equilibrium in the

measur-able space exchange economy. As{B1,. . ., Bn} is a division of X,

it suffices to show that Biisi-maximal in the budget set of

indi-viduali, Bi(), for all i ∈ N. Assume on the contrary, that for some i there existsB ∈ Bi() such that B iBi. Thus

(B) ≤ (Ai)= (Bi)= ˛i( ¯p)

andi(B)∈ Pi(i(Bi)). This preference implies that

¯ psi· i(B) > ¯psi· i(Bi)= (Bi)= ˛i( ¯p) ≥ (B) =



j ∈ N ¯ psj· j(B ∩ Bj). We thus have ¯ psi· i(B \ Bi)>



j ∈ N\{i} ¯ psj· j(B ∩ Bj).

As{B1,. . ., Bn} is a division of X, B \ Bi=∪j∈N\{i}(B∩ Bj), where

sets B∩ Bj(j∈ N \ {i}) are disjoint. It follows from the last two

rela-tions that there exists j /= i such that

¯

psi· i(B ∩ Bj)> ¯psj· j(B ∩ Bj).

This impliesi(B∩ Bj)≥ 0. The last inequality implies that the

owners of the piece B∩ Bjwould receive a higher profit by selling

this piece to individual i rather than to individual j. This contra-dicts to the construction of the division{B1,. . ., Bn} as a profit

maximizing division.

Remark B. A byproduct of the above proof is the existence of a

competitive equilibrium in an exchange economy where individu-als are free to choose from some sets of commodity bundles rather than possessing a single commodity bundle. Such economies were considered inAubin (1981).

Proof of Theorem 4.1. Define

E = {(1(A1), 2(A2), . . . , n(An))| {A1, A2, . . . , An} is a partition of X}.

By Theorem A, E⊂ Rsis a nonempty compact convex set. Set

Y = E + Rs

−andXi= Rs+ifori ∈ N as in the previous proof. As before,

define

˛(p) = max p · Y.

Define individual wealth functions by setting˛i(p) =˛(p)/n for i ∈ N.

It is easily seen that˛(p) > 0 and hence ˛i(p) > 0 for all p ∈ .

(6)

Budget sets are defined as Bi(p) = {xi∈ Xi| psi· xi≤ ˛i(p)}.

So, we have an economyE for which a competitive equilibrium is

defined in the following way: 

Definition B2. An (n + 1)-tuple (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p), where

¯

xi∈ Xix¯0= i ∈ Nx¯i∈ Y, ¯p · ¯x0= max ¯p · Y, and ¯p ∈ is a

com-petitive equilibrium in economyE, if ¯xiis a Pi-maximal element in

the budget set Bi(p) for all i∈ N.

For the economyE all of the conditions of Gale–Mas-Colell

exis-tence theorem (1975) are satisfied. So, there exists a competitive equilibrium (¯x1, ¯x2, . . . , ¯xn, ¯p) in economy E. We have

¯ x0=



i ∈ N ¯ xi∈ Y and ¯p · ¯x0= max ¯p · Y.

If ¯x0∈ E0, where, as before, E0is the Pareto frontier of Y, then ¯x0∈ E,

and hence there exists a division{B1, B2,. . ., Bn} of X such that

i(Bi)= ¯xi for i ∈ N.

As in the previous proof, define a measure on  by setting

(D) =



i ∈ N ¯ psi· i(D ∩ Bi) for D ∈ . (9) We have (Bj)= ¯psj· j(Bj)= ˛j(p) =˛(¯p)n for all j ∈ N.

We assert that division B ={B1, B2, . . ., Bn} is weak

group-envy-free and weakly Pareto efficient. Assume it is not weak group-envy-free. Then there exist N1, N2⊂ N such that |N1| = | N2|

and there is a division∪i ∈ N1Ciof∪j ∈ N2Bjsuch that Ci∈ Pi(Bi) for all i∈ N1. It follows then(Ci) >(Bi) for all i∈ N1. Summing up these

inequalities we will have(∪i ∈ N1Ci)> (∪i ∈ N1Bi). But from(9)we have

(∪i ∈ N1Ci)= (∪j ∈ N2Bj)= |N2|

n ˛(¯p) = (∪i ∈ N1Bi).

Assume now that division B is not weakly Pareto efficient. Then there exists a division C ={C1, C2,. . ., Cn} of X such that Ci∈ Pi(Bi) for

all i∈ N. Then (Ci) >i(Bi) for all i∈ N. Summing these inequalities

we will have



i∈N(Ci) >



i∈N(Bi) that is,(X) > (X), a

contradic-tion.

If ¯x0/∈ E0, then there exists ˆx0≥ ¯x0such that ˆx0∈ E0, and hence

ˆ

x0∈ E. Using the weak monotonicity assumption as in Proof of

The-orem 3.1 we reduce the situation to the case of ¯x0∈ E0.

References

Aliprantis, C., Border, K.C., 1994. Infinite Dimensional Analysis. Springer Verlag, Berlin.

Aubin, J.-P., 1981. Cooperative fuzzy games. Math. Oper. Res. 6, 1–13.

Bewley, T., 1972. Existence of equilibria in economies with infinitely many com-modities. J. Econ. Theory 4, 514–540.

Berliant, M., 1985. An equilibrium existence result for an economy with land. J. Math. Econ. 14, 53–56.

Berliant, M., Dunz, K., (1986). The welfare theorems and economics with land and a finite number of traders. Working paper, No 54, Rochester Center for Economic Research.

Berliant, M., Thomson, W., Dunz, K., 1992. On the fair division of a heterogeneous commodity. J. Math. Econ. 21, 201–216.

Berliant, M., Dunz, K., 2004. A foundation of location theory: existence of equilibrium, the welfare theorems, and the core. J. Math. Econ. 40, 593– 618.

Chambers, C.P., 2005. Allocation rules for land division. J. Econ. Theory 121, 236– 258.

Chernoff, H., 1951. An extension of a result of Liapunoff on the range of a vector measure. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 2, 722–726.

Dubins, L.E., Spanier, E.H., 1961. How to cut a cake fairly. Am. Math. Monthly 68, 1–17.

Dunz, K., 1991. On the core of a land trading game. Reg. Sci. Urban Econ. 21, 73– 88.

Gale, D., Mas-Colell, A., 1975. An equilibrium existence theorem for a general model without ordered preferences. J. Math. Econ. 2, 9–16.

Hüsseinov, F., 2008. Existence of the core in a heterogeneous divisible commodity exchange economy. Int. J. Game Theory 37, 387–395.

Liapunov, A.A., 1940. Sur les fonctions-vecteurs completement additives. Bull. Acad. Sci. USSR 4, 465–478.

Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M.D., Green, J.R., 1995. Microeconomic Theory. Oxford University Press, New-York/Oxford.

Referanslar

Benzer Belgeler

Geçit blokları ile FPGA’nın sınırları belirlendikten sonra, Xilinx DSP blokları kullanılarak DSP tasarımları gerçekleştirilebilmektedir. Standart Simulink

Kalça ekleminin harabiyeti ile sonuçlanan ve hastalarda günlük hayatlarını olumsuz etkileyen şiddetli ağrıya neden olan hastalıkların konservatif tedavilerden yarar

The overall aim of the project was to develop a joint networking and advanced research programme on critical issues of planning, management and urban heritage to strengthen

Uluslararası Türk Folklor Kongresi Başkan­ lığına bir önerge verilerek, Baş- göz ve Boratav’ın kongreden çı­ karılmalarının gerekçesi sorul­

section 3.2), due to computational and programming difficulties and to solve larger problems requires using the partitioning procedure more than 10 times. Note that, the

In this study, we used the TPA to estimate the phase of the field, since we used a quadrature birdcage coil. In fact, the limits of the TPA have been studied for the birdcage coil

Although military statistics and records were highly developed in Russia compared with the Ottoman Empire, the number of Russian troops during the Crimean War

Bu sonuçlara göre kontrol grubunda fiziksel ihmal bildirenlerde düşük BDÖ puanının olması, kardeş grubunda depresyon olmamasına rağmen fiziksel ihmal bildirenlerde