• Sonuç bulunamadı

Time-varying fairness concerns, delay, and disagreement in bargaining

N/A
N/A
Protected

Academic year: 2021

Share "Time-varying fairness concerns, delay, and disagreement in bargaining"

Copied!
14
0
0

Yükleniyor.... (view fulltext now)

Tam metin

(1)

ContentslistsavailableatScienceDirect

Journal

of

Economic

Behavior

&

Organization

jo u r n al ho me p ag e :ww w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / j e b o

Time-varying

fairness

concerns,

delay,

and

disagreement

in

bargaining

Emin

Karagözo˘glu

a,b,∗

,

Kerim

Keskin

c

aBilkentUniversity,Turkey bCESifo-Munich,Germany cKadirHasUniversity,Turkey

a

r

t

i

c

l

e

i

n

f

o

Articlehistory:

Received18September2017 Receivedinrevisedform 27November2017 Accepted3January2018 Availableonline9January2018 JELclassification: C72 C78 D03 Keywords: Bargaining Deadlineeffect Delay Disagreement Fairnessconcerns Justicesensitivity

a

b

s

t

r

a

c

t

Westudyanalternating-offers,bilateralbargaininggamewhereplayersmayderive disu-tilityfromacceptingsharesbelowwhattheydeemasfair.Moreover,weassumethatthe valuestheyattachtofairness(i.e.,theirsensitivitytoviolationsoftheirfairnessjudgments) decreaseovertime,asthedeadlineapproaches.Ourresultsofferanewexplanationto delaysanddisagreementsindynamicnegotiations.Weshowthatevenmutually compati-blefairnessjudgmentsdonotguaranteeanimmediateagreement.Wepartiallycharacterize conditionsfordelayanddisagreement,andstudythechangesinthelengthofdelayin responsetochangesinthemodelparameters.

©2018ElsevierB.V.Allrightsreserved.

1. Introduction

Delays in reaching an agreement and stalemates are ubiquitous features of real life bargaining encounters. Labora-tory experiments on bargaining games report similar observations (see Roth et al., 1988; Babcock et al., 1995; Babcock and Loewenstein, 1997; Gächter and Riedl, 2005; Karagözo˘glu and Riedl, 2015; Karagözo˘glu and Kocher, 2016; among others). Roth et al. (1988), who observed subjects’tendency to reach agreements towards the deadline, labeled this phe-nomenon as the deadline effect.1 Babcock et al. (1995), Babcock and Loewenstein (1997), Gächter and Riedl (2005), and

Karagözo˘gluandRiedl(2015)observedthatdelaysinreachingagreementsanddisagreementsarepositivelycorrelatedwiththe incompatibilitybetweenthebargainers’fairnessjudgments.Basedontheseobservations,theyinformallyarguedthat fairmind-edness, combined withbiasedandincompatiblefairness judgments,couldbeone ofthereasons behind delays,last-minute agreements,andevendisagreements.Standardbargainingmodelswithcommonknowledgeofrationality,complete/perfect

infor-∗ Correspondingauthorat:BilkentUniversity,DepartmentofEconomics,06800Bilkent,Ankara,Turkey. E-mailaddresses:karagozoglu@bilkent.edu.tr(E.Karagözo˘glu),kerim.keskin@khas.edu.tr(K.Keskin).

1Thisisalsofrequentlyobservedoutsidethelab.Forinstance,laborunionsandemployersusuallyreachagreementsjustbeforeastrikestarts,a

phenomenonknownasthe“eleventhhourdeal”.Settlementsinpre-trialnegotiationsareusuallyreachedjustbeforethecourtdate.Similarly,in2011and 2013,DemocratsandRepublicansreachedanagreementinthenegotiationsabouttheU.S.debtceiling,justbeforethedeadline.

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2018.01.002 0167-2681/©2018ElsevierB.V.Allrightsreserved.

(2)

mation,anddiscountingfailtocapturethesephenomena.Inthosemodels(seeRubinstein,1982),theplayerwhomakesthefirst offerusesalltherelevantinformationandmakesanofferthattheotherplayercannotreject.Thisresultsinanimmediateagreement. Delaysanddisagreementsinnegotiationscanhaveimportanteconomicimplications.Forinstance,strikesorlockoutsdueto disagreementsbetweenlaborandmanagement(e.g.,theNBAlockoutinthe2011–2012season,theUSAirwaysunionworkers’ strikein2014),continuingconflictsbetweencountries(e.g.,theCyprusconflict,theIsraeli-Palestinianconflict),postponeddecisions duetostalematesinpoliticalnegotiations(e.g.,delaysingovernmentformationduetolengthycoalitionnegotiationsinBelgiumin 2011andintheNetherlandsin2017),mergerandacquisitionnegotiations(e.g.,theVerizon–Yahoomerger),orlitigationnegotiations (e.g.,thePennzoilvs.Texacocase)implygreatwelfarecostsnotonlyforthenegotiatingpartiesinvolvedbutalsoforthethirdparties whohaveinterestsconnectedtothenegotiation(e.g.,fans,tvbroadcastingcompanies,sportsbrandsintheNBAlockoutexample). Therefore,understandingthefactorsthatcausebargainingdelaysanddisagreementsisofutmostimportance.Overthelastthree decades,bargainingscholarsofferedvarioustheoreticalexplanationsfordelayanddisagreements.2Asymmetricinformationorlack

ofcommonpriorsonimportantbargainingcharacteristics(e.g.,discountfactors,outsideoptions),stochasticallyevolvingmodel parameters(e.g.,stakesize),oruncertaintyregardingplayertypesandreputationalconcernsarethemainreasonsforequilibrium delayanddisagreementinthosepapers.

Inthecurrentpaper,westudyanalternating-offersbargaininggamewithaknowndeadlinebetweentwoplayerswhereplayers mayderivedisutilityfromacceptingsharesbelowwhattheydeemasfair.Moreprecisely,eachplayerhassomesubjectivejudgment regardingthefairdivisionofthepie,whichiscommonknowledge;andifshereceivesasharebelowwhatshedeemsasfair,then shederivesdisutilityfromthat.Anaturalexampleaddressedinvariousbargainingexperimentsisasfollows(seeGantneretal., 2001;BirkelandandTungodden,2014;Karagözo˘gluandRiedl,2015;BoltonandKaragözo˘glu,2016):Supposethattwoplayers,Alan andBetty,exertedeffortstojointlyproducethepietheyarebargainingover.Alan’seffortproduced70%ofthepie,whereasBetty’s effortproduced30%ofthepie.Now,Alanbelievesthattheappropriatejusticenormisequityandhencethepieshouldbedivided inproportiontotheircontributions(i.e.,70–30division);whereasBettybelievesthattheappropriatejusticenormisequalityand hencethepieshouldbedividedequally(i.e.,50–50division).Eachplayerwouldexperiencedisutilityfromreceivingsharesbelow theirfairshares(70vs.50,respectively).

Importantly,weallowtheweightstheplayersattachtofairnessconcerns(i.e.,theirsensitivitytoviolationsoftheirfairness judgments)todiminishovertime.Accordingly,asthedeadlineapproaches,theplayerscarelessandlessaboutfairnessandbecome moreandmorematerial-gain-oriented.Thismodelingchoiceisinspiredbytherecentexperimentalfindings,whichhighlightthe primacyofeconomicconcernsoverfairnessconcerns—especiallyundertime/cognitivepressure(seeMooreandLoewenstein,2004; Knochetal.,2006;KnochandFehr,2007;Halalietal.,2013;Hochmanetal.,2015;amongothers)andthetemporalinstability ofjusticesensitivity(seeFortinetal.,2016foranexcellentreview).Furthermore,itisalsoinlinewiththehabituationandcostly self-controlargumentsinthetheoreticalliterature,whichwouldimplythatanagentwhorepetitivelyreceivesastimulithatis cognitivelydisturbingorcostlytohandlestartstobecomelessresponsive(seeKaragözo˘glu,2014forhabituation;andFudenberg andLevine,2006;Dreberetal.,2016forcostlyself-control).

We,first,analyticallyshowthatdelayand/ordisagreementmayexistintheequilibriumofthisbargaininggame.Weprovide necessaryandsufficientconditionsfortheexistenceofdelayanddisagreement.Ourresultsshowthatwhetherplayerswillbeableto reachanagreementandifsowhendependonmultiplefactorssuchasplayers’fairnessjudgments,thepaceofthedecreaseintheir weightsforfairness,theidentitiesofplayers(i.e.,proposerorresponder)indifferentperiods,andthehorizonlength.Furthermore, oursimulationresultsshowthatourmodelcanproduceempiricallyrelevantoutcomepatternssuchasU-shapedorJ-shaped distributionofagreementtimes,whichareusuallyobservedindynamicbargainingexperiments(seeRothetal.,1988;Gächterand Riedl,2005;Karagözo˘gluandRiedl,2015;Sullivan,2016).Ourcomparativestaticanalysesrevealnon-trivialinteractionsbetween themodelparametersandbargainingdelay.Forinstance,moredemandingfairnessjudgmentsorstrongerconcernsforfairness mayleadtofasteragreements.Finallyandsomewhatsurprisingly,weshowthatmutuallycompatiblefairnessjudgmentsdonot guaranteeanimmediateagreement.

Itisworthwhileemphasizingthatalltherelevantinformationiscommonknowledgeinourmodel.Thereisnoincompleteor imperfectinformation.Playersareperfectlyforward-looking.3Ourmodelisthefirsttoexplainbothdelayanddisagreementina

finite-horizon,alternatingoffersbargainingframeworkwithoutresortingtousualincompleteorimperfectinformation assump-tions.Moreover,itisthefirstmodeltoformallystudytime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Tothebestofourknowledge,Birkelandand Tungodden(2014)presentthecloseststudytooursinthattheyalsoutilizefairnessconcerns.TheseauthorsworkonastaticNash bargainingmodel,withoutanytime-varyingcomponentinfairnessjudgments.Naturally,theirmodelcanexplaindisagreements, butnotdelay.

Theorganizationofthepaperisasfollows.InSection2,weintroduceourmodel.InSection3,wefirstpresentouranalytical resultsontheexistenceofequilibriuminvolvingdelayanddisagreement.Later,wepresentsimulationresultsontherelationships betweenthemodelparametersandthelengthofdelay.Section4concludes.

2. Themodel

Weinvestigateatwo-playerfinite-horizonalternatingoffersbargaininggamealaRubinstein(seeRubinstein,1982).LetN={1, 2}bethesetofplayerswhobargainoveradivisiblepie(withanormalizedsizeof1)forafinitenumberofperiodsT.Inperiodt=1, player1proposesadivisionofthepiechoosingastrategy(anoffer)from[0,1].Observingplayer1’soffer,player2chooseswhether toacceptorreject:{a,r}.Ifsheacceptstheoffer,thentheproposeddivisionisimplementedandthegameends.Incasesherejects

2 SeeRubinstein(1985),AdmatiandPerry(1987),GulandSonnenschein(1988),Cho(1990),Cramton(1991),FershtmanandSeidmann(1993),Maand

Manove(1993),JehielandMoldovanu(1995),MerloandWilson(1998),AbreuandGul(2000),Bac(2000),Yildiz(2004),FeinbergandSkrzypacz(2005), Ali(2006),SimsekandYildiz(2014),Romm(2016),Fanning(2016)amongothers.

(3)

theoffer,thegameproceedstothenextperiod.Inperiodt=2,itisplayer2’sturntomakeanoffer,choosingastrategyfrom[0, 1],afterwhichplayer1istodecidewhethertoaccept(a)orreject(r)theoffer.Ifplayer1accepts,thentheproposeddivisionis implementedandthegameends;ifsherejects,thenthegameproceedstoperiod3inwhicheverythingfollowsasinthefirstperiod. ThisbargainingprocedurecontinuesuntiloneoftheplayersacceptsanofferoruntilperiodTends.Incasetheformerhappens,each playergetssomeutilitybasedontheagreeddivision,whereasifthelatterhappens,thenthegameendswithadisagreementwhich yieldsautilityof0tobothplayers.

Players have fairness concerns. More precisely, each player iN believes that it is fair for her to receive a share ϕi∈[0,1]of thepie.If playerigetsashare xi<ϕi,thensheexperiences adecreaseintheutilityderivedfromthematerial

gain of having xi∈[0, 1].4 This type of preferences is commonly represented with an additively separable utility

func-tion in the literature (see Bolton, 1991; Fehr and Schmidt, 1999; Bolton and Ockenfels, 2000). The novel feature of our model isthe introduction of time-varying fairnessconcerns. Accordingly,each utilityfunction has different weightsfor the material gain and thedisutility comingfrom an unfair division, and theweight (relative importance) for fairness concerns weakly decreases through time. We normalize the weight of the material gain inboth utility functions to 1, and we let ˛i:{1,...,T}→[0,∞)beanon-increasingfunctionofplayeri’srelativeweightsforherfairnessconcernsateachperiod.Ifplayers

agreeonanallocation(x,1−x)atsomeperiodt∈{1,...,T},theirutilitiesfromsuchanagreementaregivenby: u1((x,1−x),t)=x−˛1(t)·max{ϕ1−x,0}

u2((x,1−x),t)=1−x−˛2(t)·max{ϕ2+x−1,0}

Playersdiscountfuturepayoffswithıi∈(0,1).Thismeansthattheutilitiesgivenabovearediscountedbyarateofıit−1when

evaluatedinthefirstperiod.Alltherelevantinformation(e.g.,fairnessconcerns,theinitialvaluesandtheevolutionoftheweights attachedtofairness,thediscountfactors,functionalforms,etc.)iscommonknowledge.WedenotethisgamebyT.

3. Theresults

Inwhatfollows,wefirstpresenttheanalyticalresultsontheexistenceofequilibrium,delay,anddisagreements.Later,wepresent simulationresultsonthelengthofdelay.

3.1. Analyticalresults

Throughoutthepaper,anequilibriummeans(purestrategy)subgameperfectNashequilibrium.Wedenotetheoffermadeby player1atsomeperiodtbyxtandtheoffermadebyplayer2atsomeperiodtbyyt.Asaconvention,nomatterwhotheproposeris, anofferalwaysindicatestheshareofplayer1.Toputitdifferently,player1proposesthesharehewantstoreceive,whereasplayer 2proposestheshareshewantstogive.Ourfirstpropositionconcernstheexistenceofequilibrium.

Proposition1. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.AnequilibriumofTexists. Proof. Tisafinite-horizon,completeinformation,extensiveformgamewithcontinuousutilityfunctionsandcompactstrategy

setsateachdecisionnode.Theexistenceresultaccordinglyfollows.

Itisworthmentioningthattheremayexistmultipleequilibriaandthatallequilibriaarepayoffequivalent:utilizingbackward induction,onecanseethatifaplayerpreferstomakeanofferthatcannotberejected,thenthereexistsauniqueoptimaloffer;but ifaplayerpreferstomakeanofferthatwillberejected,thenthereexistsinfinitelymanyoptimaloffers.Thelatterwouldleadtoa multiplicityofequilibria,whereastheformerguaranteesthatallequilibriaarepayoffequivalent.Notethattheplayersmaynotbe abletosimplyagreeontheequilibriumpayoffsinthefirstperiodsincethosepayoffsmaynotbefeasibleinthefirstperioddueto higherweightstheyattachtofairnessatthebeginningofthegame.

Oursecondpropositionconcernstheexistenceofdisagreementsanddelayedagreementsontheequilibriumpath.Forthat purpose,itisenoughtoanalyzeatwo-periodbargaininggame.

Proposition2. Let2beatwo-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Then,(i)thereexistsanequilibrium

of2withadisagreementand(ii)thereexistsanequilibriumof2withadelayedagreement(i.e.,anagreementinthesecondperiod). Proof. SeeAppendixA.

ThecorollarybelowshowsthatthesameresultsfollowforanyT-periodbargaininggame.

Corollary1. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Then,(i)thereexistsanequilibriumof

Twithadisagreementand(ii)thereexistsanequilibriumofTwithadelayedagreement(i.e.,anagreementsometimeafterthefirst

period).

Proof. TheproofsimplyfollowsfromProposition2sinceonecanaddarbitrarynumberofperiodstothetwo-periodgameanalyzed inProposition2.

4Notethatplayers’fairnessjudgmentsareself-servinginthattheydonotexperiencedisutilityiftheyreceiveasharelargerthantheirfairshare.

Introducingthecounterpartforxi>ϕiisneitheressentialforourmodelnorchangesourresultsqualitatively.Hence,weoptforsimplicity.Satisfaction

withadvantageousinequityincognitivelydemandingsituationsissupportedbyexperimentalresearch,aswell(seeFalkandFischbacher,2006;Vanden Bosetal.,2006).

(4)

TheproofofProposition2maygivetheimpressionthattheincompatibilitybetweenplayers’fairnessjudgmentsnecessitatesa delayedagreement,ifnotadisagreement.Bycontrast,Proposition3showsthatevenwhenthereisnosuchconflictbetweenfairness judgments,itispossibletohavedelayedagreements.Thepropositionfurtherindicatesthatdisagreementisimpossibleinthatcase. Proposition3. Let2beatwo-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Letϕ

1+ϕ2<1,i.e.,thereexists

anallocationwhichsatisfiesbothplayers’fairnessconcerns.Then,(i)theremaystillexistanequilibriumwithadelayedagreementbut(ii) thereexistsnoequilibriumwithdisagreement.

Proof. SeeAppendixA.

Noticethattheformerstatementisaboutapossibility.Whenthereisnoconflictbetweenplayers’fairnessjudgments,an immedi-ateagreementisgenerallyreached;however,theoppositemightalsobetrueinsomecases.Forinstance,incasethebestacceptable offerinthefirstperiodisunfairtooneoftheplayers5andtheweightsattachedtofairnessdecreasedramaticallyinthenextperiod,

thenthatplayermayprefertoproceedtothenextperiodinwhichshemayfindsuchanunfairoffermoreacceptableduetohaving alowerweightforfairnessconcerns.Thelatterstatementinthepropositionisbasedonthefactthatifplayers’fairnessjudgments arecompatible,eithertheyimmediatelyagreeoriftheydonot,theremustbeabetteralternativeinthefuture,whichcannotbea stalemate.

Proposition4presentsanecessaryandsufficientconditionfortheexistenceofadisagreementinequilibrium.Infact,itboils downtogeneralizingthecondition(*)givenintheproofofProposition2.

Proposition4. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.AnequilibriumofT involves

disagreementifandonlyif 1+˛2(T)·(1−ϕ2)

1+˛2(T) <

˛1(T)·ϕ1

1+˛1(T). Proof. SeeAppendixA.

Theleft-hand-sideoftheinequalityinthepropositionistheshareofthepiewhichyieldsautilityof0toplayer2inperiodT, therebymakingplayer2indifferentbetweenagreementanddisagreement,whereastheright-hand-sideistheshareofthepiewhich yieldsautilityof0toplayer1inthesameperiod.Accordingly,theleft-hand-siderepresentsthehighestofferplayer2iswillingto acceptinperiodTandtheright-hand-siderepresentsthelowestofferplayer1iswillingtomakeinthesameperiod.Incasethe formerislessthanthelatter,thereexistsnoofferthatisacceptabletobothplayers.Thisimpliesadisagreement.Notethatifsucha conditionissatisfiedinperiodT,similarconditionswouldbesatisfiedinanyperiodt<T.

3.1.1. TheLengthofDelay:APartialCharacterization

Anaturalquestionatthispointis:Canweidentifythelengthofdelay(orequivalently,theagreementperiod)?Itturnsoutthat writingthelengthofdelayasafunctionofthemodelparametersisfarfromtrivial;andhence,isleftforfutureresearch.Herewe takeanintermediatestep.Inordertopartiallycharacterizetheagreementperiod,wemakeuseofthefollowinginterpretation: Considerafinitehorizon,alternatingoffersbargaininggamewithnofairnessconcerns(i.e.,withstandardutilityfunctions).Inthe firstperiod,playersbargainoverasetwithalinearfrontierpassingfromtheutilitypairs(0,1)and(1,0).6Asamatteroffact,a

similarinterpretationfollowsforeachperiodwiththedifferencethatthebargainingsetinperiodtisalwayslargerthanthatin periodt+1foreveryt∈Nduetothediscountfactorıi∈(0,1)(seeFig.1).Thisisthereasonwhythereisanimmediateagreement

inthestandardmodel:supposethatplayersagreeinsomeperiodt>1andgetdiscountedutilitiesof ¯u1and ¯u2,wecaneasilysee

thatplayer1couldoffer ¯u2toplayer2inthefirstperiodandreceiveahigherutilitythan ¯u1;acontradiction.

Inourmodelwithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns,thereisanumberofpossibilitiesregardinghowtheabove-describedbargaining setschangeacrossperiods.Forinstance,ifthereisaconflictbetweenplayers’fairnessconcernsandif˛i(t)issufficientlyhighforeach

player,thenitmaybethatthebargainingsetinperiodtdoesnotincludeautilitypairgreaterthanorequalto(0,0),invectorterms (seeS1inFig.2).Insuchaperiod,weknowforsurethatthereexistsnoagreement.Ontheotherhand,when˛

i(t)issufficientlylow

foreachplayer,thenthereexistallocationsyieldingpositiveutilitiestobothplayers(seeS2inFig.2).Notethatifthisisthecasein

someperiodt,thenforeveryperiodt>t,therealwaysexistallocationsyieldingpositiveutilitiestobothplayers.Furthermore,note thatduetotime-varyingfairnessconcerns,wecannotsimplysaythatthebargainingsetinperiodtisalwayssmallerorlargerthan thebargainingsetinperiodtforsomeperiodst,t>t.Thereasonisthatalthoughthediscountfactorshrinksthebargainingsetin

thenextperiod,non-increasingfairnessconcernsexpandthebargainingset.Andtheseparametersmaybesuchthatthebargaining setsinperiodtandtdonotcontainoneanother(seeS3,S4,andS5inFig.2).

Becauseofthesedifferentformseachbargainingsetmaytake,itisaverydifficulttasktoidentifytheagreementperiodinclosed form.Thisisthereasonwhyweturntoapartialcharacterization.Westartwiththefollowingremark.

Remark1. LetStdenotethebargainingsetinperiodt.IfS1doesnotincludeautilitypairgreaterthanorequalto(0,0),i.e.,iffor

everyx∈[0,1],

x−˛1(1)·(ϕ1−x)<0 and 1−x−˛2(1)·(ϕ2+x−1)<0,

5 Althoughthereexistallocationswhichbothpartiesdeemasfair,an‘optimal’offermightbeunfairtooneofthepartiesduetotheasymmetrycreated

bytheidentityoftheproposerinthefinalperiod.

6 Althoughthemodelrestrictsplayerstochooseautilitypaironthefrontier,wecanalsoassumethatplayersareabletochoosefromthewholebargaining

(5)

Fig.1.Apossiblecollectionofbargainingsetsinthestandardmodel.

thenthereexistsdelayordisagreement.

Fromnowon,weavoidtrivialcasesandonlyconsidertheonesinwhichS1includesatleastoneutilitypairgreaterthan(0,0),

invectorterms.Inthefollowing,wedefinetwoconceptsaboutthecorrespondingbargainingsetsineachperiodandusethem toprovideadditionalconditionsforhavingadelayedagreement.First,wedefinedominationinbargainingsetsanddescribethe conditionsforSt

⊂St.

Definition1. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Aperiodtdominatesperiodt /=t

inbargainingsetsifSt ⊂St.

Thefollowingobservationsummarizestheconditionsforthebargainingsetinperiodttodominatethebargainingsetinperiod t /=t.

Observation1. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Considertwoperiodstandtsatisfying

u1



1−˛2(t)·ϕ2 1+˛2(t), ˛2(t)·ϕ2 1+˛2(t)



,t



>ıt−t 1 ·u1



1−˛2(t)·ϕ2 1+˛2(t), ˛2(t)·ϕ2 1+˛2(t)



,t



u2



˛ 1(t)·ϕ1 1+˛1(t), 1−˛1(t)·ϕ1 1+˛1(t)



,t



>ıt−t 2 ·u2



˛ 1(t)·ϕ1 1+˛1(t), 1−˛1(t)·ϕ1 1+˛1(t)



,t



. If 1−˛2(t)·ϕ2 1+˛2(t)<ϕ1 and 1−˛1(t)·ϕ1 1+˛1(t)>ϕ2,

thenperiodtdominatesperiodtinbargainingsets;andif 1−˛2(t)·ϕ2

1+˛2(t)>ϕ1

or1−˛1(t)·ϕ1

1+˛1(t) >ϕ2,

thenperiodtdominatesperiodtinbargainingsetsonlywhent<t.

Thisobservationisbasedonthefactthatdominationinbargainingsetscanbeidentifiedusingtheendpointsofthecorresponding bargainingfrontiers.Thelatterpartoftheobservationindicatesthatwhenthereexistsnostrongconflict(i.e.,whenthereexistsa utilitypairwhichsatisfiesthefairnessconcernofoneplayerandyieldsapositiveutilityfortheotherplayer),onlyanearlierperiod candominateaparticularperiodinbargainingsets.7Utilizingthisobservation,wepresentthefollowingnecessaryconditionfora

delayedagreement.

Remark2. Ifforeveryi∈{1,2}andeveryt∈{1,...,T}, ˛i(t)

˛i(1)>ı t−1 i ,

7RemembertheresultinProposition3:evenwhenthereisnoconflictinplayers’fairnessconcerns,t=1doesnotnecessarilydominatethefollowing

(6)

Fig.2. Apossiblecollectionofbargainingsetsinourmodel.

thent=1dominatesalltheotherperiodsinbargainingsets.Accordingly,thereisanimmediateagreementinanyequilibrium ofT.Inordertohaveadelayedagreementinequilibrium,theinequalityabovemustbeviolatedforsomei{1,2}andsome

t∈{1,...,T}.

Inotherwords,iftheinequalityinRemark2issatisfiedforbothplayersandforanyperiod,thenthediscountfactorsaresufficiently lowsuchthatdiscountingshrinksthebargainingsetsinthefollowingperiodsmorethannon-increasingfairnessconcernsexpands thebargainingsetintherespectiveperiod.Thisimpliesthatthefirstperioddominatesalltheotherperiodsinbargainingsets,so thatplayerswouldbebetteroffagreeinginthefirstperiod.

Below,weprovidethedefinitionofdominationthroughtheunionofbargainingsets,whichwillbeusefulin(partially)identifying theagreementperiod.

Definition2. LetTbeaT-period,bilateralbargaininggamewithtime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Acollectionofperiodst1,...,tk

dominatesanotherperiodtthroughtheunionofbargainingsetsif St



i∈{1,...,k}S ti

.

Furthermore,aperiodtisundominated,ifnocollectionofperiodsdominatesperiodtthroughtheunionofbargainingsets. Now,wearereadytodescribeapropertyoftheagreementperiodandanothersufficientconditionfordelay.

Remark3. InaT-periodbargaininggame,theagreementperiodt*isundominated.8Thus,ifthefirstperiodisdominatedbysome

collectionofperiods,thenthereexistsdelayordisagreement;andifthereexistsauniqueperiod ˆtwhichisundominated,then ˆtis theagreementperiod.

Asmentionedabove,theremaybemultipleundominatedperiodsinthepresenceoftime-varyingfairnessconcerns.Inthatcase, inwhichperiodplayerswillagreedependsonmultiplefactorssuchastheidentityoftheproposersintheundominatedperiods, theshapeofbargainingsetsintheundominatedperiods,theendpointsofbargainingfrontiersintheundominatedperiods,etc.For suchsituations,wearguethatsolvingfortheequilibriumistheonlywaytodeterminetheagreementperiod.

3.1.2. TheLengthofDelay:AnIllustrativeExample

Wenowprovideathree-periodexampleinwhichwecharacterizethesubgameperfectNashequilibrium.Thisistounderstand howtheequilibriumconditionsinourmodelappearandhowthevaluesofmodelparametersdeterminewhethertherewillbe anagreementandifsowhen.Notethat(i)anyT-periodgamecanbeanalyzedinasimilarmannerforanyoddT ∈Nand(ii)the equilibriumanalysisbelowcanbeextendedtothecaseswhereTiseven.

Example.Considerthebargaininggame3andassumethatthedisagreementconditionpresentedinProposition4isnotsatisfied.

AlthoughT=3,westicktogeneralnotationinthefollowinganalysis.

ConsiderperiodTinwhichplayer1istheproposer.Theanalysisforheroptimalofferhasalreadybeenmadeintheproofof Proposition4.Giventheassumptionof“nodisagreement”specifiedabove,player1offers

x∗ T=

1+˛2(T)·(1−ϕ2)

1+˛2(T)

(7)

whichwillbeacceptedbyplayer2.

ConsiderperiodT−1inwhichplayer2istheproposer.Sheanticipatesthatifherofferisrejected,thenshewillreceiveautility of0inperiodT,whereasplayer1willreceiveautilityofı1·u1((x∗T,1−x∗T),T).Accordingly,player2makesanoffersoastomake

player1indifferentbetweenaandr,ifsuchanofferyieldsplayer2autilitynotlessthan0.Wedivideourequilibriumanalysisinto sixcases:

Forthesecases,wedefine mT−1=ı1x ∗ T+˛1(T−1)·ϕ1 1+˛1(T−1) and nT−1=ı1· [x∗ T−˛1(T)·(ϕ1−x∗T)]+˛1(T−1)·ϕ1 1+˛1(T−1) . CaseA[ϕ1≤ı1x∗T≤x∗Tandu2((ı1xT∗,1−ı1x∗T),T−1)≥0]:

Inthiscase,player1’sofferint=Tisfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityofx∗

T.Player2makesthefollowingoffer

y∗

T−1=ı1x∗T.

CaseB[ϕ1≤ı1x∗T≤x∗Tandu2((ı1x∗T,1−ı1x∗T),T−1)<0]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer1yieldsplayer2anegativeutility.Hence,player2canmakeanyofferless thanı1x∗T,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer1.

CaseC[ı1x∗T≤ϕ1≤x∗Tandu2((mT−1,1−mT−1),T−1)≥0]:

Inthiscase,player1’sofferint=Tisfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityofx∗

T.Player2makesthefollowingoffer

y∗

T−1−˛1(T−1)·(ϕ1−y∗T−1)=ı1x∗T

y∗

T−1=mT−1.

CaseD[ı1x∗T≤ϕ1≤x∗Tandu2((mT−1,1−mT−1),T−1)<0]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer1yieldsplayer2anegativeutility.Hence,player2canmakeanyofferless thanmT−1,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer1.

CaseE[ϕ1≥x∗Tandu2((nT−1,1−nT−1),T−1)≥0]:

Inthiscase,player1’sofferint=Tisunfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityofx∗

T−˛1(T)·(ϕ1−x∗T).Player2makesthe

followingoffer y∗ T−1−˛1(T−1)·(ϕ1−y∗T−1)=ı1·[x∗T−˛1(T)·(ϕ1−x∗T)] y∗ T−1=nT−1. CaseF[ϕ1≥x∗Tandu2((nT−1,1−nT−1),T−1)<0]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer1yieldsplayer2anegativeutility.Hence,player2canmakeanyofferless thannT−1,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer1.

Tosumup,player2’sbestofferisdescribedbythefollowingpiecewiseset-valuedfunction:9

y∗ T−1=

ı1x∗T ifCaseA mT−1 ifCaseC nT−1 ifCaseE [0,ı1x∗T) ifCaseB [0,mT−1) ifCaseD [0,nT−1) ifCaseF

ConsiderperiodT2inwhichplayer1istheproposer.IncasesA,C,andEabove:player1anticipatesthatifherofferisrejected, thenshewillreceiveautilityof

UT−1≡ı1·u1((y∗T−1,1−y∗T−1),T−1),

whereasplayer2willreceiveautilityof ı2·u2((y∗T−1,1−y∗T−1),T−1).

Accordingly,player1makesanoffersoastomakeplayer2indifferentbetweenaandr,ifsuchanofferyieldsplayer1autilitynot lessthanUT−1.Wedivideourequilibriumanalysisintosixcases:

(8)

Forthesecases,wedefine kT−2=ı2·(1−y∗T−1), mT−2= 1+˛2(T−2)·(1−ϕ2)−ı2·(1−y∗T−1) 1+˛2(T−2) and nT−2= 1+˛2(T−2)·(1−ϕ2)−ı2·[1−y∗T−1−˛2(T−1)·(ϕ2+y∗T−1−1)] 1+˛2(T−2) . Case1A[ϕ2≤kT−2≤1−y∗T−1andu1((kT−2,1−kT−2),T−2)≥UT−1]:

Inthiscase,player2’sofferint=T−1isfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityof1−y∗

T−1.Player1makesthefollowingoffer

x∗

T−2=kT−2.

Case1B[ϕ2≤kT−2≤1−y∗T−1andu1((kT−2,1−kT−2),T−2)<UT−1]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer2yieldsplayer1anundesirableutility.Hence,player1canmakeanyoffer higherthankT−2,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer2.

Case1C[kT−2≤ϕ2≤1−y∗T−1andu1((mT−2,1−mT−2),T−2)≥UT−1]:

Inthiscase,player2’sofferint=T−1isfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityof1−y∗

T−1.Player1makesthefollowingoffer

1−x∗

T−2−˛2(T−2)·(ϕ2+x∗T−2−1)=ı2·(1−yT−1∗ )

x∗

T−2=mT−2.

Case1D[kT−2≤ϕ2≤1−y∗T−1andu1((mT−2,1−mT−2),T−2)<UT−1]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer2yieldsplayer1anundesirableutility.Hence,player1canmakeanyoffer higherthanmT−2,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer2.

Case1E[ϕ2≥1−y∗T−1andu1((nT−2,1−nT−2),T−2)≥UT−1]:

Inthiscase,player2’sofferint=T−1isunfairforher.Suchanofferyieldsherautilityof1−y∗

T−1−˛2(T−1)·(ϕ2+y∗T−1−1).

Player1makesthefollowingoffer 1−x∗

T−2−˛2(T−2)·(ϕ2+x∗T−2−1)=ı2·[1−y∗T−1−˛2(T−1)·(ϕ2+y∗T−1−1)]

x∗

T−2=nT−2.

Case1F[ϕ2≥1−y∗T−1andu1((nT−2,1−nT−2),T−2)<UT−1]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer2yieldsplayer1anundesirableutility.Hence,player1canmakeanyoffer higherthannT−2,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer2.

IncasesB,D,andFabove:player1anticipatesthatifherofferisrejected,thenshewillreceiveautilityof VT−1≡ı21·u1((x∗T,1−x∗T),T),

whereasplayer2willreceiveautilityof0.Accordingly,player1makesanoffersoastomakeplayer2indifferentbetweenaandr,if suchanofferyieldsplayer1autilitynotlessthanVT−1.Wedivideourequilibriumanalysisintotwocases:

Forthesecases,wedefine pT−2=1+˛12(+T˛−2)·(1−ϕ2)

2(T−2) . Case2A[u1((pT−2,1−pT−2),T−2)≥VT−1]:

Inthiscase,player2’sofferint=T−1isirrelevantandplayer1’sofferinperiodTyieldsplayer2autilityof0.Player1makesthe followingoffer

x∗

T−2=pT−2.

Case2B[u1((pT−2,1−pT−2),T−2)<VT−1]:

Itturnsoutthatanofferthatwillbeacceptedbyplayer2yieldsplayer1anundesirableutility.Hence,player1canmakeanyoffer higherthanpT−2,andanysuchofferwillberejectedbyplayer2.

(9)

Tosumup,player1’sbestofferisdescribedbythefollowingpiecewiseset-valuedfunction: x∗ T−2=

kT−2 ifCase1A mT−2 ifCase1C nT−2 ifCase1E pT−2 ifCase2A (kT−2,1] ifCase1B (mT−2,1] ifCase1D (nT−2,1] ifCase1F (pT−2,1] ifCase2B

Thiscompletesouranalysisofequilibriuminclosedform.Now,weconsiderdifferentsetsofparametervaluesinordertoillustrate thatagreementinanyperiodispossible.Wefirstfix

ϕ1=ϕ2=0.8 and ı1=ı2=0.8

If˛1(T)=˛2(T)=2,thenitfollowsbyProposition4thatwehaveadisagreement.Instead,assumingthat

˛1(T) =˛2(T)=1

˛1(T−1) =˛2(T−1)=2

wehaveadelayedagreementinperiodT=3.Assumingthat ˛1(T) =˛2(T)=2/3

˛1(T−1) =˛2(T−1)=3/4

˛1(T−2) =˛2(T−2)=2

wehaveadelayedagreementinperiodT−1=2.Finally,consideringstandardpreferenceswithnofairnessconcerns,wewouldhave animmediateagreementinperiodT2=1.

3.2. Simulations

Inthissubsection,wereportsimulationresultsidentifyingtheagreementperiodandanalyzehowitrespondstochangesinthe modelparameters.10Forthesakeoftractability,weconsiderthefollowingfunctionalformfor˛

i(·):

˛i(t)=iati

foreveryi{1,2},andusethefollowingvaluesforthemodelparameters T ∈ {20,21}

ıi ∈ {0.95}

ϕi ∈ {0.1,0.2,...,0.9,1}

i ∈ {6,24}

ai ∈ {0.1,0.2,...,0.8,0.9}

foreveryi∈{1,2},whichcorrespondstoatotalof64,800numericalresults.11

ThenumberofperiodsTischoseninordertocapturesufficientamountofvariabilityintheagreementperiods.The func-tionalformfor˛i andthecorrespondingparametervaluescoverafairlywiderangeof interestingsituations.For instance,if

ai=0.1and i=6,thenplayer i alwaysvalues materialgain morethanshe valuesfairness; ifai=0.9and i=24,thenplayer

i cares aboutfairnessat the beginningof thegame so much thather materialgain never becomes relativelymore impor-tantthroughoutthegame;andinalloftheremainingcases,fairnessisrelativelymorevaluableforplayeriatthebeginning, butitbecomesrelativelylessvaluablesomewhereduringthegameasthedeadlineapproaches.Theswitchingperiod signif-icantly depends ontheactualvaluesof these parameters:ai governs thespeed of decreaseinplayer i’sweight for fairness

concerns and i determines whethersuch a speed is enough to make thematerial gain relativelymore important before

theend.

10ThesimulationsareconductedinVisualStudiousingC++astheprogramminglanguage.

11Duetospacelimitations,wereportasmallsubsetoftheseresultsinFigs.3and5.Allequilibriumagreementperiodscanbefoundintheonlineappendix

(10)

Fig.3.TheagreementperiodswhenT=20.(Boldfacenumbersinrowsandcolumnsarethevaluesforϕ1andϕ2,respectively.)

Toprovideaclearunderstanding,herewerestrictthesetofparametervaluesandreporttheresultsinFig.3.12Asitcanbeseen

inthisfigure,weobserveawiderangeofagreementperiods;withanimmediateagreementwhenplayers’beliefabouttheirfair sharesaresufficientlylow,andwiththeagreementperiodgenerallyincreasingasϕi,ai,oriincreasereachingamaximumvalueof

19whenϕ1=ϕ2=0.8,a1=a2=0.8,and1=1=24.

Below,wepresenttwoobservationsfromoursimulationresults.Thefirstobservationisaboutacommonlyreportedfindingin theexperimental/empiricalliteratureonbargaining:thedistributionofagreementperiodsisU-orJ-shaped,meaningthatplayers mostlyagreeeitherclosetothebeginningorclosetothedeadline,withlatterbeingobservedmorefrequently,buttheyrarelyagree inthemiddleofthegame(seeRothetal.,1988;Kessler,1996;GächterandRiedl,2005;Karagözo˘gluandRiedl,2015;Sullivan,2016; VassermanandYildiz,2016,amongothers).Thisobservationcanbesupportedbyourtheoreticalmodelforsomevaluesofmodel parameters.Forexample,considera1=a2=0.9and1=2=6whenT=20andı1=ı2=0.95.Settingperiods1–7asthebeginningpart

andperiods15–20astheendpartofthegame,andassumingthateachplayer’sbeliefaboutherfairshareisuniformlydistributed over{0.2,...,0.9},13wecanarguethatthedistributionofagreementperiodsisU-shaped(seethechartontheleftinFig.4).Asfor

anotherexample,considera1=a2=0.8,1=2=24,andϕ1,ϕ2∈{0.3,...,0.9}keepingtheotherparametervaluesunchanged.Now,

thedistributionofagreementperiodsbecomesJ-shaped(seethechartontherightinFig.4).

Thesecondobservationisthattheagreementperiodisnotnecessarilymonotonicinaplayer’sbeliefaboutherfairshareϕior

inherfairnessweightparameterai.Thatis,asoneoftheseparametersincreasesforaplayer,itmayturnoutthatplayersreachan

agreementmorequickly.Forexample,fixinga1=a2=0.8and1=2=6,playersagreeinthe15thperiodwhenϕ1=0.8andϕ2=0.5;

whereastheyagreeinthe13thperiodwhenϕ1remainstobe0.8andϕ2increasesto0.6.Althoughsuchcasesarequiteuncommon

inthedomaincoveredbytheparametervaluesweused,theydoexist,preventingustoreachageneralmonotonicityresult. Theintuitionbehindthissomewhatcounterintuitiveresultisasfollows.Considerthenumericalexampleabove.Wecanseevia backwardinductionthatplayerswouldagreeinthe17thperiodyieldinganexpectedutilityof0.3399toplayer2inbothcases.From thatagreementplayer1’sexpectedutilityisequalto0.2727incase(i)ϕ2=0.5andto0.2667incase(ii)ϕ2=0.6.Simply,inthelatter

case,player1hastoofferahighersharetoplayer2inordertomakeherindifferentbetweenacceptingandrejectingtheoffer,so thatplayer1’sownexpectedutilityturnsouttobelower.Now,incase(i),player1hasachancetoofferanamountyielding0.3399 toplayer2inthe15thperiodincreasingherownexpectedutilityto0.2910.Thus,playersagreeinthe15thperiod.Ontheother hand,incase(ii),player1doesnotwishtoofferanexpectedutilityof0.3399toplayer2inthe15thperiod.Thereasonisthatplayer 2’sfairamountisnowhighersothatanunfairdivisionwouldgiveherahigherdisutility(incomparisontotheformercase),sothat makingplayer2indifferentbetweenacceptingandrejectingturnsoutnottobebeneficialforplayer1.Thus,theydonotagreeinthe 15thperiod.Finally,inthe13thperiodofbothcases(i)and(ii),player1istoofferanexpectedutilityof0.3399toplayer2inorderto makeherindifferentbetweenacceptingandrejectingtheoffer.However,incase(i),player1wouldmaketheofferonlyifityields anexpectedutilitynolessthan0.2910toherself;whereasincase(ii),shewouldmaketheofferonlyifityieldsanexpectedutility

12 ForT=21,forwhichthelastproposerisplayer1,theresultsarerelegatedtotheAppendixA. 13 Arguably,casesinwhichϕ

(11)

Fig.4.U-orJ-shapedagreements.

nolessthan0.2667toherself.Giventhattheofferthatmakesplayer2indifferentyieldsanexpectedutilityof0.2854toplayer1, theofferismadeincase(ii)leadingtoanagreementinthe13thperiod,butnotmadeincase(i).Asimilarresultaswellasasimilar interpretationarevalidforai.14

4. Conclusion

Westudyafinitehorizonbargaininggamebetweentwoplayerswhovaluenotonlytheabsoluteamounttheyreceivebutalsothe relativeshare.Thenoveltyofourmodelisthattheweightsplayersattachtofairnessdecreaseovertimeasthedeadlineapproaches. Thus,asthepushcomestoshove(i.e.,asthedeadlineapproachesandlosingthemoneyonthetablebecomesmoresalient),players becomemorefocusedonmaterialgainsandlessfocusedonfairness.Thismodelingassumptionisinspiredbytherecentexperimental studiesonhotvs.coldpsychologicalstates,therelativeprimacyofeconomicvs.socialconcerns,timepressure,andthetemporal instabilityofjusticesensitivity.

Ourresultsshedlightontheinfluenceoffairnessjudgmentsondelays,last-minuteagreements,anddisagreementsindynamic bargainingsituations.We,first,analyticallyshowthatdelayordisagreementmayexistintheequilibriumpath.Then,weprovide necessaryandsufficientconditionsfordisagreementanddelay.Wealsofindthatmutuallycompatiblefairnessjudgmentsdonot guaranteeanimmediateagreement.Ouranalyticalresultsshowthatwhetherplayerswillbeabletoreachanagreementandifso whendependsonmultiplefactorssuchasplayers’fairnessjudgments,thepaceofthedecreaseintheirweightsforfairness,the iden-titiesofplayers(i.e.,proposerorresponder)indifferentperiods,andthehorizonlength.Ourmodelproducesempiricallyrelevant outcomepatternssuchasU-shapedorJ-shapeddistributionofagreementtimes,whicharefrequentlyobservedindynamic bargain-ingexperiments.Finally,oursimulationresultsrevealsomeinterestingcomparativestaticresults.Forinstance,moredemanding fairnessjudgmentsorstrongerconcernsforfairnessmayleadtofasteragreements.

Herewepresentedanempiricallyinspiredmodelofbargaining,whichsuccessfullymatchesmultipleregularitiesinthe experi-mental/empiricaldata.Tothebestofourknowledge,thisisthefirstfinite-horizonalternating-offersbargainingmodelthatproduces delayanddisagreementinequilibriumwithoutresortingtousualincompleteorimperfectinformationassumptions.15Obviously,

tobetterunderstandtherelationshipbetweentime-varyingfairnessconcernsanddelay/disagreementinbargaining,experiments particularlydesignedtotestthepredictionsofourmodelshouldbeconducted.

Thisisafirststepinincorporatingtime-varyingfairnessjudgmentsintobargainingmodels.Afurtherstepwouldbetomodelthe micro-foundationsoftime-varyingfairnessjudgments.Toachievethisgoal,webelievethatexperimentsinvestigatingthechangesin brainactivityintheregionsthatreacttounfairness—asaproxyforchangesinthevaluepeopleattachtofairness—duringnegotiations withfMRIstudiesoralternativemethodssuchasskinconductancewouldbenaturalcomplements.

Acknowledgments

Wewouldliketothanktheeditor,twoanonymousreviewers,andGaryCharnessforusefulcommentsandsuggestions.Weare gratefultoHamideTuranforherhelpinwritingthecodeusedforthesimulationresults.Wealsothankaudiencesatthe“Bargaining: TheoryandExperiments”workshopatBilkentUniversityandthe2ndTurkishExperimentalandBehavioralEconomicsWorkshop at ˙IstanbulBilgiUniversity.EminKaragözo˘gluthanksTÜB˙ITAK(TheScientificandTechnologicalResearchCouncilofTurkey)forthe post-doctoralresearchfellowship,andMassachusettsInstituteofTechnology,DepartmentofEconomicsfortheirhospitality.The usualdisclaimersapply.

AppendixA.

ProofofProposition2. Considert=2inwhichplayer2istheproposer.Shemakesanoffer,whichmakesplayer1indifferent betweenplayingaandr.Notingthatplayingrwouldyieldplayer1autilityof0,wefindplayer2’soptimalofferasfollows:

14Asamatteroffact,onecanfindnumericalexamplesforthenon-monotonicityina

iintherestrictedsetofexampleswehavereportedinFigs.3and5. 15Incorporatinguncertaintyintotheevolutionofplayers’fairnesspreferencesovertimemaybeareasonableextension.Nevertheless,itwould

(12)

y∗ 2−˛1(2)·(ϕ1−y∗2)=0 y∗ 2= ˛1(2)·ϕ1 1+˛1(2)

Noticethatplayer2wouldnotprefertomakethisoffer,iftheremainingpieamountyieldsheranegativeutility;i.e.,if16

1−y∗

2−˛2(2)·(ϕ2+y∗2−1)<0. (*)

Ifthisisthecase,player2makessomeofferlessthany∗

2,whichwillthenberejectedbyplayer1.So,therewillnotbeanyagreement

int=2.Ifthisisnotthecase,therewillbeanagreementontheallocation(y∗ 2,1−y2∗).

Now,tocompletetheproof,wemustshowthatthebargainingproceedstot=2.Considert=1.Notethatplayer1istheproposer andthatsheanticipatestheoutcomeoft=2.Shemakesanofferthatmakesplayer2indifferentbetweenplayingaandr.Notingthat playingrwouldyieldplayer2autilityof

u2((y∗2,1−y∗2),2)

int=2,wedividetheproblemintotwocases: (i) ϕ2≤1−y∗2 and (ii) ϕ2>1−y∗2.

Incase(i),player2’sutilityis1−y∗

2.Dividethiscaseintotwosubcases:

(i.a) ϕ2≤ı2·(1−y∗2) and (i.b) ϕ2>ı2·(1−y∗2).

Incase(i.a),player1’soptimalofferis: x∗

1=1−ı2·(1−y∗2)

Incase(i.b),player1’soptimaloffercanbefoundbythefollowing: 1−x∗ 1−˛2(1)·(ϕ2+x1∗−1)=ı2·(1−y∗2) x∗ 1= 1+˛2(1)·(1−ϕ2)−ı2·(1−y∗2) 1+˛2(1)

Incase(ii),player2’sutilityis1−y∗

2−˛2(2)·(ϕ2+y∗2−1).Player1’soptimaloffer—whichshouldbeunfairforplayer2—canbe

foundbythefollowing: 1−x∗ 1−˛2(1)·(ϕ2+x∗1−1)=ı2·[1−y∗2−˛2(2)·(ϕ2+y∗2−1)] x∗ 1= 1+˛2(1)·(1−ϕ2)−ı2·[1−y∗2−˛2(2)·(ϕ2+y∗2−1)] 1+˛2(1) Tosumup,ifx∗

1yieldsanegativeutilitytoplayer1int=1foroneoftheabovecases,thenforthatparticularcase,thereis

noagreementinthefirstperiod.Notethatthisispossible,if˛1(1)issufficientlyhigh.Ifthishappensincase(i),thenthereisan

agreementint=2.Ifthishappensincase(ii),thenthereisanagreementint=2iftheequation(*)isnotsatisfied,andthereis disagreementiftheequation(*)issatisfied.

ProofofProposition3. Fortheformer,weprovideanexampleinwhichthereexistsdelay.Consideratwo-periodmodelwith ı1 =ı2=0.9,

ϕ1 =ϕ2=0.4,

˛1(2) =˛2(2)=0.25,and

˛1(1) =˛2(1)=1.

Considert=2inwhichplayer2istheproposer.Shemakesanoffersoastomakeplayer1indifferentbetweenaandr.Thisoffer isy

2=0.08,whichyieldsautilityof0toplayer1andadiscountedutilityof0.828toplayer2.Now,considert=1.Anticipatingthe

outcomeoft=2,player1’soffercouldbetotake0.172forherself,andtherebymakingplayer2indifferentbetweenplayingaandr. However,suchanofferwouldyieldautilityof0.172−0.228=−0.056<0.Then,player1wouldprefermakinganofferwhichplayer 2rejects.Hence,inequilibrium,agreementisreachedwithdelay.

Forthelatter,supposethatthereexistsdisagreement.ThisalsomeansthatplayersdidnotagreeuntilperiodT(i.e.,theyreached thefinalperiod).ConsiderperiodT.Withoutlossofgenerality,assumethatplayer1istheproposer.Inthisperiodthereexistsanoffer forplayer1whichyieldsapositiveutilitytoherselfandautilityof0toplayer2,sinceϕ1+ϕ2<1byassumption.Sincedisagreement

16 Thisisnotnecessarilyplayer2’sutility,becauseif1y

2isfairforher,thenherutilitywouldbe1−y∗2.Insuchacase,player2getsapositiveutilityfor

(13)

yieldsautilityof0tobothplayers,player1woulddeviatetosuchanofferandplayer2wouldaccept.Thisisacontradiction.Hence, thereisalwaysanagreement.

ProofofProposition4. AssumethatTisodd(forevenT,similarargumentsfollow).ConsiderperiodTinwhichplayer1isthe proposer.Shemakesanofferthatmakesplayer2indifferentbetweenplayingaandr.Notingthatplayingrwouldyieldplayer2a utilityof0,wefindplayer1’soptimalofferasfollows:

1−x∗ T−˛2(T)·(ϕ2+xT∗−1)=0 x∗ T= 1+˛2(T)·(1−ϕ2) 1+˛2(T)

Now,ifsuchanofferisnotbeneficialforplayer1,i.e.,if x∗ T−˛1(T)·(ϕ1−x∗T)<0 x∗ T<˛1 (T)·ϕ1 1+˛1(T)

thenplayer1wouldoffersomethinghigherthanx∗

Tandplayer2wouldreject.

Tosumup,if 1+˛2(T)·(1−ϕ2)

1+˛2(T) <

˛1(T)·ϕ1

1+˛1(T),

thereisnoagreementinthefinalperiod.Noticethatifthisisthecase,thentherewouldnotbeanagreementinthepreviousperiods either.Tobemoreprecise,ifthereisnoallocationthatyieldsautilitypairgreaterthan(0,0)inperiodT,thenthereisnoallocation thatyieldssuchautilitypairinthepreviousperiods.Thisisbecause˛i(t)≥˛i(T)foreveryi∈{1,2}andt<T.Thiscompletesthe

proof.

SimulationresultswhenT=21:

Fig.5. TheagreementperiodswhenT=21.(Boldfacenumbersinrowsandcolumnsarethevaluesforϕ1andϕ2,respectively.)

References

Abreu,D.,Gul,F.,2000.Bargainingandreputation.Econometrica68(1),85–87.

Admati,A.D.,Perry,M.,1987.Strategicdelayinbargaining.Rev.Econ.Stud.54(3),345–364.

(14)

Babcock,L.,Loewenstein,G.,1997.Explainingbargainingimpasse:theroleofself-servingbiases.J.Econ.Perspect.11(1),109–126. Babcock,L.,Loewenstein,G.,Issacharoff,S.,Camerer,C.,1995.Biasedjudgmentsoffairnessinbargaining.Am.Econ.Rev.85(5),1337–1343. Bac,M.,2000.Signalingbargainingpower:strategicdelayversusrestrictedoffers.Econ.Theory16(1),227–237.

Birkeland,S.,Tungodden,B.,2014.Fairnessmotivationinbargaining:amatterofprinciple.TheoryDecis.77(1),125–151.

Bolton,G.E.,Karagözo˘glu,E.,2016.Ontheinfluenceofhardleverageinasoftleveragebargaininggame:theimportanceofcredibleclaims.GamesEcon. Behav.99,164–179.

Bolton,G.E.,Ockenfels,A.,2000.ERC:atheoryofequity,reciprocity,andcompetition.Am.Econ.Rev.90(1),166–193. Bolton,G.E.,1991.Acomparativemodelofbargaining:theoryandevidence.Am.Econ.Rev.81(5),1096–1136. Cho,I.K.,1990.Uncertaintyanddelayinbargaining.Rev.Econ.Stud.57(4),575–595.

Cramton,P.,1991.Dynamicbargainingwithtransactioncosts.Manage.Sci.37(10),1221–1233.

Dreber,A.,Fudenberg,D.,Levine,D.K.,Rand,D.,2016.Self-control,socialpreferencesandtheeffectofdelayedPayments.WorkingPaper.MIT. Falk,A.,Fischbacher,U.,2006.Atheoryofreciprocity.GamesEcon.Behav.54,293–315.

Fanning,J.,2016.Reputationalbargaininganddeadlines.Econometrica84(3),1131–1179.

Fehr,E.,Schmidt,K.M.,1999.Atheoryoffairness,competition,andcooperation.Q.J.Econ.114(3),817–868. Feinberg,Y.,Skrzypacz,A.,2005.Uncertaintyaboutuncertaintyanddelayinbargaining.Econometrica73(1),63–91.

Fershtman,C.,Seidmann,D.,1993.Deadlineeffectsandinefficientdelayinbargainingwithendogenouscommitment.J.Econ.Theory60(2),306–321. Fortin,M.,Cojuharenco,I.,Patient,D.,German,H.,2016.Itistimeforjustice:howtimechangeswhatweknowaboutjusticejudgmentsandjustice

effects.J.Organ.Behav.37,S30–S56.

Fudenberg,D.,Levine,D.K.,2006.Adualselfmodelofimpulsecontrol.Am.Econ.Rev.96(5),1449–1476. Gächter,S.,Riedl,A.,2005.Moralpropertyrightsinbargainingwithinfeasibleclaims.Manage.Sci.51(2),249–263.

Gantner,A.,Güth,W.,Königstein,M.,2001.Equitablechoicesinbargaininggameswithjointproduction.J.Econ.Behav.Organ.46(2),209–225. Gul,F.,Sonnenschein,H.,1988.Ondelayinbargainingwithone-sideduncertainty.Econometrica56(3),601–611.

Halali,E.,Bereby-Meyer,Y.,Ockenfels,A.,2013.Isitallabouttheself?Theeffectofself-controldepletiononultimatumgameproposers.Front.Hum. Neurosci.7,240.

Hochman,G.,Ayal,S.,Ariely,D.,2015.Fairnessrequiresdeliberation:theprimacyofeconomicoversocialconsiderations.Front.Psychol.6,747. Jehiel,P.,Moldovanu,B.,1995.Negativeexternalitiesmaycausedelayinnegotiation.Econometrica63(6),1321–1335.

Karagözo˘glu,E.,Kocher,M.,2016.Bargainingundertimepressure,CESifoWorkingPaper#5685.

Karagözo˘glu,E.,Riedl,A.,2015.Performanceinformation,productionuncertainty,andsubjectiveentitlementsinbargaining.Manage.Sci.61(11), 2611–2626.

Karagözo˘glu,E.,2014.Adynamicmodelofdissonancereductioninamodularmind.J.Neurosci.Psychol.Econ.7(1),15–32. Kessler,D.,1996.Institutionalcausesofdelayinthesettlementoflegaldisputes.J.LawEcon.Organ.12(2),432–460.

Knoch,D.,Fehr,E.,2007.Resistingthepoweroftemptations:therightprefrontalcortexandself-control.Ann.N.Y.Acad.Sci.1104,123–134. Knoch,D.,Pasqual-Leone,A.,Meyer,K.,Treyer,V.,Fehr,E.,2006.Diminishingreciprocalfairnessbydisruptingtherightprefrontalcortex.Science314,

829–832.

Ma,C.A.,Manove,M.,1993.Bargainingwithdeadlinesandimperfectplayercontrol.Econometrica61(6),1313–1339. Merlo,A.,Wilson,R.,1998.Efficientdelaysinastochasticmodelofbargaining.Econ.Theory11(1),39–55.

Moore,D.,Loewenstein,G.,2004.Self-interest,automaticity,andthepsychologyofconflictofinterest.Soc.JusticeRes.17,189–202. Romm,A.,2016.Buildingreputationattheedgeofacliff.WorkingPaper.HebrewUniversityofJerusalem.

Roth,A.E.,Murnighan,J.K.,Schoumaker,F.,1988.Thedeadlineeffectinbargaining:someexperimentalevidence.Am.Econ.Rev.78(4),806–823. Rubinstein,A.,1982.Perfectequilibriuminabargainingmodel.Econometrica50(1),97–110.

Rubinstein,A.,1985.ABargainingmodelwithincompleteinformationabouttimepreferences.Econometrica53(5),1151–1172. Simsek,A.,Yildiz,M.,2014.Durability,Deadline,andelectioneffectsinbargaining.WorkingPaper.MIT.

Sullivan,S.P.,2016.Whywaittosettle?Anexperimentaltestoftheasymmetric-informationhypothesis.J.LawEcon.59(3),497–525.

VandenBos,K.,Peters,S.L.,Bobocel,D.R.,Ybema,J.F.,2006.Onpreferencesanddoingtherightthing:Satisfactionwithadvantageousinequitywhen cognitiveprocessingislimited.J.Exp.Soc.Psychol.42(3),273–289.

Vasserman,S.,Yildiz,M.,2016.Pretrialnegotiationsunderoptimism.WorkingPaper.MIT. Yildiz,M.,2004.Waitingtopersuade.Q.J.Econ.119(1),223–248.

Referanslar

Benzer Belgeler

The turning range of the indicator to be selected must include the vertical region of the titration curve, not the horizontal region.. Thus, the color change

Given 6 pictures of different people, and 3 descriptions of 3 of these pictures, the student will be able to identify which description belongs to which picture and be able

In order to determine the number of moles of reactant B remaining at time t, for every mole of A that consumed, b/a moles of B must consumed; therefore, the number of moles of B

While the retailer’s stock quantity decision determines the total supply chain profit, the manufacturer’s contract parameter decision has three roles:..  Inducing the retailer’s

Practically, this study aims at giving hotel managers in accounting, marketing and relationship marketing insight to perceived price fairness and its impact on customer

The autonomy of the female self in late 19 th century and freedom from marriage are some of the themes that will be discussed in class in relation to the story.. Students will

 Students will be asked to report their observations and results within the scope of the application to the test report immediately given to them at the end

Taking into account the relatively limited reserves of glycogen in muscles and liver, and the high demands, placed on these endogenous carbohydrate reserves by